Lukes 2005 POWER: A RADICAL VIEW

1INTRODUCTION

●Power: A Radical View (hereafter PRV). It was a contribution to an ongoing debate, mainly among American political scientists and sociologists, about an interesting question: how to think about power theoretically and how to study it empirically.

●we need to think about power broadly rather than narrowly in three dimensions rather than one or two -and that we need to attend to those aspects of power that arc least accessible to observation: that, indeed, power is at its most effective when least observable.

○imp

●Questions of powerlessness and domination, and of the connections between them, were at the heart of the debate to which PRV contributed.

●Two books, in particular, were much discussed in the 1950s and 1960s: The Power Elite by C. Wright Mills (Mills 1956) and Community Power Structure: A Study of Decision Makers by Floyd Hunter (Hunter 1953).

●Mills's book was both a fiery polemic and a work of social science. Alan Wolfe, in his afterword to its republication in 2000 justly comments that 'the very passionate convictions of C. Wright Mills drove him to develop a better scientific grasp on American society than his more objective and clinical contemporaries',

●Hunter's book, though much more low-key and conventionally professional (Mills described it as a 'workmanlike book' by a 'straightforward investigator who docs not deceive himself by bad writing'), made claims similar to those of Mills about elite control at local levels of US society.

●These striking depictions of elite domination over powerless populations produced a reaction on the part of a group of political scientists and theorists centered on Yale University.

●In an article entitled 'A Critique of the Ruling Elite Model', published in the American Political Science Review in 1958, Robert Dahl was caustic and crisp.

●Dahl's critique was straightforward. What needed to be done was clear: The hypothesis of the existence of a ruling elite can be strictly tested only if: 1. The hypothetical ruling elite is a well-defined group; 2. There is a fair sample of cases involving key political decisions in which the preferences of the hypothetical ruling elite run counter to those of any other likely group that might be suggested; 3. In such cases, the preferences of the elite regularly prevail. (Dahl: 1958: 466)

●Dahl's clas sic study Who Governs? {Dahl 1961), which studied power and decision-making in the city of New Haven in the 1950s, and spawned a whole literature of community power studies.

●power was seen as relative to several, separate, single issues and bound to the local context of its exercise,

●Power was here conceived as intentional and active: indeed, it was 'measured' by studying its exercise -by ascertaining the frequency of who wins and who loses in respect of such issues, that is, who prevails in decision-making situations.

●Those situations arc situations of conflict between interests, where interests are conceived as overt preferences, ... and the exercise of power consists in overcoming opposition, that is, defeating contrary preferences.

●it was claimed that, since different actors and different interest groups prevail in different issue-areas, there is no overall 'ruling elite' and power is distributed pluralistically. More generally, these studies were aimed at testing the robustness of American democracy at the local level, which, by revealing a plurality of different winners over diverse key issues, they claimed largely to vindicate.

●Critics challenged in various ways the rather complacent picture of pluralist democracy (Duncan and Lukes 1964, Walker 1966, Bachrach 1967), they doubted its descriptive accuracy (Morriss 1972, Domhoff1978), and they criticized the 'realistic' (as opposed to 'utopian'), minimally demanding conception of 'democracy' that the pluralists had adopted,

●This conception was derived from Joseph Schumpeter's revision of 'classical' views of democracy. For Schumpeter, and his pluralist followers, democracy should now be seen as 'that institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people's vote' (Schumpeter 1962(1950]: 269).

●Power, argued Peter Bachrachand Morton Baratz, had a 'second face' unperceived by the pluralists and undetectable by their methods of inquiry. Power was not solely reflected in concrete decisions; the researcher must also consider the chance that some person or association could limit decision-making

●How was the researcher to investigate such 'influencing' (which they called 'nondecisionmaking') especially if it went beyond behind-thescenes agenda-setting, incorporation or co-optation of potential adversaries and the like and could be 'unconscious' and include the influencing of' values' and the effects of 'rituals'?

●Bachrach and Baratz retreated somewhat, stating that there must always be observable conflict if their second face of power is to be revealed; without it one can only assume there to be 'consensus on the prevailing allocation of values'.

●But why should one exclude the possibility that power may be at work in such a way as to secure consent and thus prevent conflict from arising?

●Confronting the failure of revolution in the West in his prison cell in Fascist Italy, Gramsci had grappled with the question: how is consent to capitalist exploitation secured under contemporary conditions, in particular democratic ones? How was such consent to be understood?

●Joseph Schumpeter's shrewd observation concerning Lincoln's dictum that you can't fool all the people all the time: that it is enough to fool them in the short run, since history 'consists of a succession of short-run situations that may alter the course of events for good' (Schumpeter 1962[ 1950]: 264).

●A few individuals can be mistaken, but delusions cannot be perpetuated on a mass scale. [2]

●The consent which underlies reproduction of capitalist relations does not consist of individual states of mind but of behavioral characteristics of' organizations.

●Consent, thus understood, 'corresponds to the real interests of those consenting', it is always conditional, there are limits beyond which it will not be granted and 'beyond these limits there maybe crises' (Przeworski 1985:136, 145-6). [3]

●The questions to which Gramsci's hegemony promised answers had become live issues in the early 1970s, when PRV was written.

●What explained the persistence of capitalism and the cohesion of liberal democracies? Where were the limits of consent beyond which crises would occur?

●Today it seems plausible to claim that the large, central issue which that slender text addressed -how is willing compliance to domination secured? -has become ever more pertinent and demanding or an answer.

●'if ordinary domination so consistently hurts the well-defined interests of subordinate groups, why do subordinates comply? Why don't they rebel continuously, or at least resist all along the way?'

●Tilly most helpfully provides a checklist of the available answers to the problem:

●1. The premise is incorrect: subordinates are actually rebelling continuously, but in covert ways.

●2. Subordinates actually get something in return for their subordination, something that is sufficient to make them acquiesce most of the time.

●3. Through the pursuit of other valued ends such as esteem or identity, subordinates become implicated in systems that exploit or oppress them. (1n some versions, no. 3 becomes identical to no. 2.)

●4. As a result of mystification, repression, or the sheer unavailability of alternative ideological frames, subordinates remain unaware of their true interests.

●5. Force and inertia hold subordinates in place.

●6. Resistance and rebellion are costly; most subordinates lack the necessary means.

●7. All of the above. (Tilly 1991: 594)

●(7) is, clearly, correct: the other answers should not be seen as mutually exclusive (or, indeed, jointly exhaustive).

●(2) is (as Przeworski's materialist interpretation of Gramsci suggests) a major part of the explanation of the persistence of capitalism, but also, one should add, of every socio-economic system.

●(2) and (3) together point to the importance of focusing on actors' multiple, interacting and conflicting interests.

●it is (4), (5) and (6) that relate specifically to power and the modes of its exercise. As Tilly remarks, (5) emphasizes coercion and (6) scant resources. It is, however, (4) that pinpoints the so-called 'third dimension' of power the power 'to prevent people, to what ever degree, from having grievances by shaping their perceptions, cognitions and preferences in such a way that they accept their role in the existing order of things'.

●no view of power can be adequate unless it can offer an account of this kind of power.

●its mistakes and inadequacies are, I believe, rather instructive, and rendered the more so in prose that makes them clearly visible (for, as the seventeenth-century naturalist John Ray observed, 'He that uses many words for explaining any subject, doth, like the cuttlefish, hide himself for the most part, in his own ink').

○gq

●There are two subsequent chapters. The first of these (Chapter 2) broadens the discussion by situating the reprinted text and its claims on a map of the conceptual terrain that power occupies.

●the topic of PRV, and much writing and thinking about power, is more specific: it concerns power over another or others and, more specifically still, power as domination.

●PRV focuses on this and asks: how do the powerful secure the compliance of those they dominate~ and, more specifically, how do they secure their willing compliance?

●the ultra-radical answer offered to this question by Michel Foucault, whose massively influential writings about power have been taken to imply that there is no escaping domination, that it is 'everywhere' and there is no freedom from it or reasoning independent of it.

●there is no need to accept this ultra-radicalism, which derives from the rhetoric rather than the substance of Foucault's work~ work which has generated major new insights and much valuable research into modern forms of domination.

●Chapter 3 defends and elaborates PRV's answer to the question, but only after indicating some of its mistakes and inadequacies.

●It was a mistake to define power by 'saying that A exercises power over B when A affects B in a manner contrary to B's interests'.

●Power is a capacity not the exercise of that capacity (it may never be, and never need to be, exercised); and you can be powerful by satisfying and advancing others' interests:

●power as domination, is only one species of power.

●Moreover, it was inadequate in confining the discussion to binary relations between actors assumed to have unitary interests, failing to consider the ways in which everyone's interests arc multiple, conflicting and of different kinds.

●The defence consists in making the case for the existence of power as the imposition of internal constraints.

●I consider and rebut two kinds of objection: first, James Scott's argument that such power is non-existent or extremely rare, because the dominated arc always and everywhere resisting, covertly or overtly; and

●second, Jon Elster's idea that willing compliance to domination simply cannot be brought about by such power.

●the workings of power, leading those subject to it to sec their condition as 'natural' and even to value it, and to fail to recognize the sources of their desires and beliefs. These and other mechanisms constitute power's third dimension when it works against people's interests by misleading them, thereby distorting their judgment.

●there is, I argue, nothing inherently illiberal or paternalist about these notions, which, suitably refined, remain crucial to understanding the third dimension of power.

21. POWER: A RADICAL VIEW

●1 Introduction

○This chapter presents a conceptual analysis of power.

○radical in both the theoretical and political senses

○In the course of my argument, I shall touch on a number of issues methodological, theoretical and political.

○Among the methodological issues are the limits of behaviourism, the role of values in explanation, and methodological individualism.

○Among the theoretical issues arc questions about the limits or bias of pluralism, about false consciousness and about real interests.

○Among the political issues arc the famous three key issue areas studied by Robert Dahl (Dahl 1961) in New Haven /urban redevelopment, public education and political nominations), poverty and race relations in Baltimore, and air pollution.

○The argument starts by considering a view of power and related concepts which has deep historical roots (notably in the thought of Max Weber) and achieved great influence among American political scientists in the 1960s through the work of Dahl and his fellow pluralists.

○That view was criticized as superficial and restrictive, and as leading to an unjustified celebration of American pluralism, which it portrayed as meeting the requirements of democracy, notably by Peter Bachrach and Morton S. Baratz in a famous and influential article, 'The Two Faces of Power' (1962) and a second article (Bachrach and Baratz 1963), which were later incorporated (in modified form) in their book Power and Poverty (1970).

○Their argument was in turn subjected to vigorous counter-attack by the pluralists, especially Nelson Polsby (1968), Raymond Wolfinger (1971 a, I971 b) and RichardMerelman (1968a, 1968h);

○it has also attracted some very interesting defences, such as that by Frederick Frey (1971) and at least one extremely interesting empirical application, in Matthew Crenson's book The Un-Politics of Air Pollution (Crenson 1971).

○the pluralists' view was indeed inadequate for the reasons Bachrach and Baratz advance, and that their view gets further, but that it in turn does not get far enough and is in need of radical toughening.

○My strategy will be to sketch three conceptual maps, which will, 1 hope, reveal the distinguishing features of these three views of power:

○the view of the pluralists (which I shall call the o11c-dimensional view); the view of their critics (which I shall call the two-dimensional view); and a third view of power (which I shall call the three-dimensional view).

●2 The One-Dimensional View

○This is often called the 'pluralist' view of power, but that label is already misleading, since it is the aim of Dahl, Polsby, Wolfinger and others to demonstrate that power (as they identify it) is, in fact, distributed pluralistically

○Their view yields elitist conclusions when applied to elitist decision-making structures, and pluralist conclusions when applied to pluralist decision-making structures

○In his early article 'The Concept of power', Dahl describes his 'intuitive idea of power' as 'something like this: A has power over B to the extent that he can get B to do something that B would not otherwise do' (Dahl 1957, in Bell, Edwards and Harrison Wagner (eds) 1969: 80).

○A little later in the same article he describes his 'intuitive view of the power relation' slightly differently: it seemed, he writes, 'to involve a successful attempt by A to get to do something he would not otherwise do' (ibid., p. 82).

○Dahl's central method in Who Governs? is to 'determine for each decision which participants had initiated alternatives that were finally adopted, had vetoed alternatives initiated by others, or had proposed alternatives that were turned down. These actions were then tabulated as individual "successes" or "defeats". The participants with the greatest proportion of successes out of the total number of successes were then considered to be the most influential' (Dahl 1961: 336).

○The stress here is on the study of concrete, observable behaviour.

○Thus the pluralist methodology, in Merelman's words, 'studied actual behavior, stressed operational definitions, and turned up evidence. Most important, it seemed to produce reliable conclusions which met the canons of science' (Merelman l968a: 451).

■imp

○(It should be noted that among pluralists, 'power', 'influence', etc., tend to be used interchangeably, on the assumption that there is a 'primitive notion that seems to lie behind all of these concepts' (Dahl 1957, in Bell, Edwards and Harrison Wagner (eds) 1969: 80). Who Governs? speaks mainly of 'influence', while Polsby speaks mainly of 'power'.)

■- Note Loc. 285 | Added on Thursday, August 20, 2015, 06:06 AM if i took apluralist approach i would track proposals and rulings and counterproposals etc to see who wins out.

○The focus on observable behaviour in identifying power involves the pluralists in studying decision-making as their central task.

○Polsby writes one can conceive of 'power' -'influence' and 'control' are serviceable synonyms -as the capacity of one actor to do something affecting another actor, which changes the probable pattern of specified future events. This can be envisaged most easily in a decision-making situation. (1963: 3-4)

○he argues that identifying 'who prevails in decision-making' seems 'the best way to determine which individuals and groups have "more" power in social life,

○it is assumed that the 'decisions' involve 'direct', i.e. actual and observable, conflict.

○The pluralists speak of the decisions being about issues in selected (key] 'issue-areas' the:-assumption again being that such issues an: controversial and involve actual conflict.

○So we have seen that the pluralists see their focus on behaviour in the making of decisions over key or important issues as involving actual, observable conflict.

○in Who Governs? Dahl is quite sensitive to the operation of power or influence in the absence of conflict:

○the text of Who Governs? is more subtle and profound than the general conceptual and methodological pronouncements of its author and his colleagues;

○Conflict, according to that view, is assumed to be crucial in providing an experimental test of power attributions: without it the exercise of power will, it seems to be thought, fail to show up.

○What is the conflict between? The answer is: between preferences, that arc assumed to be consciously made, exhibited in actions, and thus to be discovered by observing people's behaviour.

○Furthermore, the pluralists assume that interests arc to be understood as policy preferences -so that a conflict of interests is equivalent to a conflict of preferences.

○They arc opposed to any suggestion that interests might be unarticulated or unobservable, and above all, to the idea that people might actually be mistaken about, or unaware of: their own interests.

○Thus I conclude that this first, one-dimensional, view of power involves a focus on behaviour in the making of decisions on issues over which there is an observable conflict of (subjective) interests, seen as express policy preferences, revealed by political participation.

■- Note Loc. 322 | Added on Thursday, August 20, 2015, 06:12 AM imp summary of one d view