Welfare Economics
Topic 10. The theoretical foundations of cost-effectiveness analysis*
Key reading: see reading list + references in these slides.
Today’s lecture:
- Critiques of welfarism
- Alternative paradigms:
- Non-welfarism (Sen)
- Extra-welfarism (Culyer)
- Communitarianism (Mooney)
- Critiques of extra welfarism
- The consistency of SWO between welfarist & extra welfarist approaches.
* CEA is interpreted here as including both CUA and CEA – i.e. any non- CBA (and thus non-welfarist) approach to economic evaluation.
- The welfarist (i.e. welfare economics) approach to SWO: some characteristics
- Individualism: a ranking of social states is achieved by the effect of each state on individuals’ utilities.
- Utility maximisation: by each individual/household.
→ precludes ‘counterpreferential’ choices i.e. individuals might contribute to some common good which might result in lowering their own utility. [Mooney 2002]
- Consequentialism: processes are not valued in themselves, but are instrumental towards some outcome. Sources of utility restricted to consumption of goods/services.
- Welfarism: Sen’s critique, and ‘non-welfarism’
- Individuals are different in terms of their ability to convert commodities into wellbeing. Even if goods were allocated equally across individuals, this would not necessarily lead to equal utility.
- Characteristics of people:
- Functionings: ‘what he or she manages to be’
- Capabilities: ‘freedoms; opportunities to choose’
- Sen on utility:
- Physical condition neglect/ valuation neglect: ‘realistic desires’.
- Measurement taken too far (“ ‘waiting for toto’ may not be a cunning strategy in a practical exercise…”)
- Extra welfarism (EW)
- Culyer: the objective function to be maximised shifts from utility to health.
- Maximisation of health, subject to the budget constraint, the basis upon which states are ordered.
→ dispute over what ‘extra-‘ as opposed to ‘non-welfarism’ actually means. [see Tsuchiya and Williams 2001].
→ both involve a rejection of social choices based on individual utilities; EW in theory is consistent with a wide range of quite dissimilar approaches.
e.g. why choose ‘health’ as the maximand?
→ based on an ‘exernal judgement’.
e.g., that health is agreed to be the principal output of health care services.
- In principle, EW admits a wide range non-utility arguments other than health (e.g. bearing on the characteristics of people) into the social ranking.
- Its practical interpretation in CEA/CUA has evolved in a rather specific way.
- Critiques of extra welfarism
[see Birch and Donaldson 2002; Mooney 2002; Tsuchiya and Williams 2001]
- The assumption that health is the only argument in the objective function is only one of many possible assumptions that might be defined as EW.
- Mooney [2002]: contends that both W and EW share common problems
(a) individualism: individuals’ preferences determine weights
(b) consequentialism (narrowly so under EW; e.g. excludes ‘process of care’ utility)
(c) cannot accommodate differences between groups e.g. in valuation, or ‘constructs’, of health.
Mooney’s point (a) could be debated. Tsuchiya and Williams (2001) argue that:
- The values of individuals who are gaining/losing QALYs is not the key feature of EW.
- Indeed individual’s values (of those affected) are generally rejected in favour of population values.
- The values used in QALYs are population-based and applied uniformly across all affected people regardless of their individual valuations.
[Tsuchiya & Williams 2001]
Question for discussion:
What does efficiency mean under the non-welfarist and extra-welfarist paradigms?
- Not clear where Sen’s critique leaves us vis a vis rankings of states
- Is ‘efficiency’ (max. QALYs) under EW consistent with Pareto efficiency?
In one sense (e.g. study question 13) it is.
But…
- ‘better’/’worse off’ from whose perspective?
- Does Pareto require QALYs to be based on the valuation of states by the individuals concerned?
- Communitarianism [Mooney 2002]
Communities, as well as individuals, are relevant – and community values may be different from the aggregation of individual values.
Is ‘society’ more than a collection of individuals?
→ Suggests eliciting community preferences and allocating resources in manner that respects differences in valuations between groups.
- But what/who defines what the relevant ‘communities’ are?
- The focus is on equity; but what does ‘efficiency’ mean in this context? (see related debate in HE between Sculpher & Gafni and Robinson & Parkin on sub-group analysis)
- Welfarism and extra welfarism: a bridge too far?
- Maximisation of QALYs subject to a health budget reveals an implicit valuation of a QALY
→ if an option ‘accepted’ its ICER is the minimum value placed on a QALY by decision makers, given a fixed budget.
Might this differ from society’s willingness to pay to gain a QALY?
- If a constant WTP for QALYs existed, this would enable the results from CUA to be re-expressed in CBA.
- But requires very restrictive conditions on utility functions for equivalence to be established.
Recommended reading on the relationship between the theoretic foundations of CBA & CEA
Dolan,P., Edlin, E. (2002) Is it really possible to build a bridge between CBA and CEA? JHE 21:827-843
Birch S., Donaldson C. (2002) Valuing the benefits and costs of health care programmes: where’s the extra in extra welfarism? Soc Sci Med 56(5):1121-1133.
Tsuchiya, A., Williams A. (2001) Welfare economics and economic evaluation. Ch 2 in: Drummond and McGuire.