The Philosophy of Social Research

The Philosophy of Social Research

John A. Hughes, Wesley W. Sharrock

Chapter 5

.

.

.

Although that strand of the interpretative tradition represented by Weber recognised the partiality of social scientific accounts, and hermeneutics their inevitability, the phenomenological tradition did not abandon the quest for the indubitable grounds of knowledge but sought it in a different place to that of positivism. Knowledge, for phenomenology, is an act of consciousness (see Natanson 1970, Luckman 197S. Anderson et al. 1987). To be conscious is to be conscious of something. For Husserl (1859-1938), the German philosopher who founded the school of phenomenology, the 'world' means a world experienced and made meaningful by acts of consciousness. It is through these alone that the world is given and presented to us. This is as true for science as it is for any other mode of knowing. The subject matter of science, for example, is a system of constructs resulting from conceptualisations idealisations, mathematisations, and so on, based on and derived from a 'pregiven' everyday experience. The prime task of phenomenology is to describe this everyday experience of the 'life world': the world as given in immediate experience and independent of and prior to any scientific or other interpretation. Admittedly, 'life worlds' belong to specific sociohistorical groupings. Our world, that is the everyday world of the peoples of modern societies in the late twentieth century for example, is a world seen through the lens of modern science and different, in significant respects, from the 'life worlds' of the peoples of Ancient Greece. However, no special privilege attaches to any particular 'life world' since these are shaped by sociohistorical circumstances and there can be no historically or socially independent standard by which to determine which conceptions of the world are superior to others. For Husserl, however, a 'transcendental phenomenology' could be developed as a universal theory of consciousness. Such an 'ontology of the life world' would be an a priori science of the universal structures of the perceptual world and would, therefore, enable us to derive any particular sociocultural product from these structures, including science and logic. If such a theory were possible, it would perform the same role that positivism envisaged for the neutral observation language; that is, a noninterpreted basis for knowledge.

For our purposes, the important figure in this tradition is Alfred Schutz who elaborated and modified Husserl's work (Schutz 1962). However, Schutz's starting point was Weber's view that it was possible to provide sociological explanations adequate at both the level of meaning and the level of causality. Schutz regarded Weber's ambition as admirable but felt that he had failed to provide the necessary philosophical premises of an interpretative social science. So, in turning to Husserl's philosophical method and his analysis of the 'life world', Schutz aimed at building the ontological framework for an interpretative social science by treating the concept of understanding as the problem which, though Weber identified, he failed to examine thoroughly enough.

Borrowing from Husserl, Schutz argued that the 'life world' of ordinary understandings is carried into the scientific world but in a manner which leaves it unexamined. The reality that the social sciences take as their topic has its origins in the 'life world', and it is this which both Weber and the positivists failed to realise. To place interpretative social science on a firmer footing, it is necessary to examine the character of daily life as the outcome of the activities of social actors. Central to Schutz's analysis is the 'postulate of subjective interpretation' which requires that social scientific accounts have to treat social actors as conscious beings whose activities have meaning for them and others. The social reality in which action takes place is the outcome of the interpretations made and courses of action undertaken by social actors. The 'objects' which this postulate makes available for study within this intersubjective 'life world' of everyday life are presented to us as an objectified system of shared designations and expressive forms. It is world of everyday life as lived and experienced through 'common sense' and displaying the 'natural attitude', that is, the attitude of the world of everyday life. Under this attitude the world is 'taken for granted'. Social actors do not question the meaningful structure of this world, do not theorise or philosophise about it, or doubt its existence: it is a world which is 'there' and dealt with in a practical manner. For example, in the course of our daily lives we have to take so many things for granted - for instance, that the sun will rise in the morning, that the cinema we plan to go to in the evening will still be there, that the work we left to do will still be on the desk tomorrow, that the car is still in the garage, that the road to work will not suddenly have changed direction, that the letter we posted yesterday will be delivered, and so on and so on - in order to construct the daily activities that we ordinarily engage in. This does not mean that things will always go to plan or that our expectations will not sometimes be confounded. We may discover that our car is not in the garage where it was left last night. But we do not conclude by this that its nature has been changed so that a car has some intermittent existence and flickers in and out of being, sometimes being there and sometimes not. We are more likely to make the usual assumption that the car remains in continuous existence and that if it is not where it was left then it is somewhere else, that it has been stolen or, perhaps, that it was actually left somewhere else and that we had temporarily forgotten. It is not something to theorise about or something which will provoke us to raise ontological questions about the nature of reality. The meaningful structure of the 'life world' is not questioned but taken for granted. The task within the 'natural attitude' is to live in the world as practical rather than theoretical or philosophical creatures.

The world has meaning because of the intentionality of consciousness. For most of the time, what persons are doing is self-evidently meaningful. Meanings are intersubjectively shared. We make sense of our own actions and those of others through a 'stock of knowledge' that is held in common, that we inherit and learn as members of society. Though such knowledge has the tonalities of our personal biography and is continually changing, its own intersubjective structure is familiar. As Husserl emphasised, we do not experience a stream of sense data as, for example, the logical positivists would have it, but experience objects as constituted for us in consciousness, such as cars, books, TVs, houses, Jon, bicycles, curries, and so on. The structure of this 'life world' is displayed through 'typifications' constructed out of whatever relevances arise from the actor's interests and purposes 'at hand'. As used by Schutz such typifications would include the universal and relatively stable as well as the more specific and changing.

As said, the primary world in which social actors live is an inter-subjective one of everyday life, a world governed by the natural attitude with its pragmatic motives and interests. In addition, actors live in other worlds of 'finite provinces of meaning', such as those of art, religious experience, dreams, childhood, and so on, each with a particular cognitive style.7 What Schutz means by this is not that we can simply imagine the world as we choose, but that each province of meaning has its own, though not unique in all respects, structure of relevances, and that the available 'stocks of knowledge' enable us to bestow 'factuality' in different ways. The paramount reality is, however, that of daily life. Of special concern to us is the world of scientific theory. This style is that of the disinterested observer who is only

concerned with problems and solutions valid in their own right for everyone, at any place, and at any time, wherever and whenever certain conditions, from the assumptions of which he starts, prevail. The 'leap' into theoretical thought involves the resolution of the individual to suspend his subjective point of view.

(Schutz 1962: 248)

The private and pragmatic concerns of everyday life are bracketed away; that is, put on one side as irrelevant for the duration of involvement in theoretical work. Sciences, both natural and social, adopt a theoretic attitude to their subject matter. They are not primarily concerned with practical consequences except as these are theoretically given. Scientific relevances are determined by the problem at hand and the procedures of the science concerned rather than those of everyday life. In the scientific attitude, as opposed to the requirements of the 'natural attitude', anything - save the existence of the external world itself - can be doubted and, accordingly, subject to investigation and analysis.

It is in this way that Schutz faces up to what he sees as the basic epistemological problem of social science, namely, how, as sciences of subjective meanings, are they possible? Like all sciences, they seek to make objective meaning claims, but in the case of the social sciences these have to be within the context of the human activity which has created them and which cannot be understood apart from these. Schutz's resolution of the difficulty is to argue that the social sciences must recognise that difference between social actors' experience of daily life and social actors as constituted as the objects of social science. This difference is required in order to make subjectivity available under the theoretic attitude. The social scientist is concerned with 'typical' schemes of actions, using simplified, abstracted and generalised versions of social actors, models which are 'lifeless fictions', 'constructs', 'ideal types', 'puppets' or 'homunculi' created by the social scientist. These models are constructed according to the postulates of logical consistency, subjective interpretation and adequacy. The first of these proposes that the construct must conform to the requirements of formal logic, the second that it must incorporate within it a model of the human mind and its typical contents such that the observed facts can be seen as the outcome of its operation. The third postulate suggests a principle of objectivity, namely, that the construct must be formulated in such a way as to be understandable to the actor using his or her own common sense.

It is the third postulate which addresses the problem which has been a major theme of this chapter, namely, the relationship between actors' concepts and those of the social scientist. Positivism's attempt to evade the socially grounded nature of knowledge by trying to formulate a neutral observation language created tensions between actors' conceptions and those of social science. And, of course, for some, Marx and Durkheim being the classic examples, this very disjuncture between the world as understood by actors and the world as discovered by the application of social science was seen as the expected outcome of such a science. Schutz, following Weber, wants to give actors' standards and concepts a much more salient role as a yardstick for the adequacy of social scientific understanding: a point which we shall develop in the next chapter in a discussion of Winch. The social scientist's interest and purpose is to display the meanings that enter into actors' worlds. Various devices, the 'ideal type', 'homunculi', or whatever, are important to this. 'Objectivity' and 'truth' are established within 'life worlds' and their socially organised settings and there is no question of one form of knowledge being absolutely superior to any other.

The important connection between Schutz's phenomenology and social research is the influence it has had on the origins of ethnomethodology as developed by Harold Garfinkel who, as Lazarsfeld tried to with positivism, sought to turn a philosophical doctrine into a methodology for social science.8 Although Schutz shared the aspirations of his mentor, Husserl, of constructing a 'transcendental analytic' of knowledge through philosophical inquiry, ethnomethodology is focused on the empirical analysis of the practical reasonings through which members produce the common-sense features of social life. It is interested in the properties of intersubjectivity as these are exhibited by social actors in the course of their activities in the day-to-day world (see, e.g. Button 1991, Anderson and Sharrock 1986, Garfinkel 1967).

Conclusion

What we have tried to do in this chapter is review some of the social philosophies which have tried to come to terms with the fact that the members of society themselves live within a world which has sense and meaning for them. It is recognition of this which presents the problem of the relationship between the sense of the world for social actors and social scientific concepts: a tension between the relationship between the social sciences and their subject matter. Research methods, where it might be said that philosophical conceptions get their hands dirty, as it were, reflect these tensions since their ability to do the job required of them by empirical researchers depends, in its turn, on the researcher's own commitments to one or the other of these philosophies.

As we saw in connection with the critique of positivist research methods earlier in this chapter, the argument is as much about the fundamental issue of the subject matter of social science as it is about the validity of the techniques and methods of social research itself. Though there is a case to be made that even by their own standards such methods do not work, there is also the equally important issue of the nature of the phenomena to be investigated and this will, or ought to, have a considerable bearing upon the means of investigation and the kind of knowledge that we require. Although interpretative philosophies of social science, as we have termed them, reject the positivist conception of science, not all of them by any means abandon the idea that social science needs secure foundations as well as the means of endowing intellectual rigour to inquiries. It is in this latter regard that we can understand Weber's treatment of verstehen and the 'ideal type', for example; that is, as ways of making the messy concreteness of the sociohistorical world amenable to rigorous empirical investigation.