On Living Mirrors and Mites: Leibniz’s Encounter with Pascal on Infinity and Living Things circa 1696.[1]
1. Introduction
Throughout his life, Leibniz hada keen interest in Pascal’s work. The evidence collected over the past century by scholars such as Baruzi[2], Grua, Mesnard,[3] andrecentlypresented by Frédéric de Buzon and Maria Rosa Antognazza, clearlyshows that, from early in his career, Leibniz was very well informed about Pascal’s work.[4]For example, we know thatLeibniz had already bought a copy of Pascal’s Pensées by 1671 (just a year after its publication).[5] In a letter to Graevious of 1671, he speaks of Pensées as a “small book of gold” (libellum aureolum) which “by the profoundness of its thought and the elegance of explication compares with any of the greatest men” (A 2.1 193). Before his arrival in Paris in 1672, and certainly during his stay there until 1676, Leibniz was in contact with the Jansenist circle (including Arnauld, Nicole, Saint Amour, Roannez, and Gilberte Pascal) and was also associated with a group loyal to Pascal (“les pascalins”, as Mesnard calles them). In 1673, Leibniz conducted a study of Pascal’s Letters to A. Detonvile.Pascal’s mathematical work, referred to Leibniz by Huygens, was one of the most important sources for his mathematical studies in 1673-76, leading to his early development of the calculus.[6]
In the beginning of 1673, Leibniz was busy developing a calculating machine expressly designed to supersede Pascal’s own calculating machine in performing automatic multiplication, division, and extraction of square and cube roots, in addition to summation and subtraction.[7] In 1675, Leibniz received Pascal’s unedited manuscripts from E. Périer (A 1, 253), which he studied with Tschirnhaus, and then recommended for publication in 1676.[8]This marks the last two years of Leibniz’s stay in Paris (1675-76) as a particularly intense period in Leibniz’s reception of Pascal’s work (which was, of course, only one among his many interests during these years).[9]
Pascal’s work continued to play a subtle and complex role in Leibniz’s thought. Among other things, Pascal certainly was, for Leibniz, a source of inspiration, as well as a source both for comparison and of a certain degree of competition. WhileLeibniz was clearly impressed with Pascal’s mathematical and experimental work,[10] his reaction tohisphilosophical work and methodological remarks were much more nuanced and critical.[11]The present paper focuses on a specific text – acomment Leibniz makes onfragment 22 of Pascal’s Penséesin the Port-Royal edition, 1670, thenentitledConnaissance générale de l’homme.However brief, this comment is of great interest – both philosophical and historical.[12]
Leibniz’scomment was published by Gaston Grua under the title Double infinité chez Pascal et Monade.[13] In this text, Leibniz refers to Pascal’s notion of theinfinitely large and infinitely small and to the way Pascaluses infinity to describe living beings through the example of a mite (ciron). In his comment, Leibniz argues that Pascal did not go far enough in employing infinity, and, in contrast to Pascal’s mite, he employsa completely differentimage – that of a living mirror (miroir vivant) –as anillustration of a living being. The present papercompares these evocative images and draws some conclusions concerning the similarities anddifferences between Leibniz’s and Pascal’s employment of infinity in capturing some essential features of living beings through their respective use of the images.
Although not yet published in English (in print), this text has been the object of studies and commentaries in German and especially in French (more details in the next section). Ithas recently been revisited, reedited, and published by Frédéric de Buzon, with an appendix presenting a new reconstruction of the text.[14]We know, for the following reasons, that Leibniz composed the text sometime around 1696: the reference to his “system of pre-established harmony, which has just recently appeared on the scene” dates the textto shortly after the New System (1695), and the text contains the word ‘monad’, which appears in Leibniz’s writings in this period, as well as the expression “a living mirror” (miroir vivant). While the figure of a mirror appears in earlier texts, such as the Discourse on Metaphysics as well as in Leibniz’s Paris Notes, the term miroir vivant appears only later—in this note, in his correspondence with Sophie (1696), in his correspondence with de Volder, as well asin texts such as the Monadology (§ 56) and the Principles of Nature and Grace(§ 3), among others.[15]I am unaware of earlier occurrences of the expression.
The composition of this text circa 1696, however, presents something of a puzzle: if Leibniz knew Pascal’s Penséeswell from 1671, why did he compose this reaction to Pascal only 25 years later? Is there anything in Leibniz’s development that could account for this text at this time, given that he had been commenting on Pascal’s work throughout his career? More specifically, what prompts him to see Pascal’s remarks on infinity as the entry point (uneentrée) into his philosophical system at this point of time?[16] I will address this question towards the end of the article.
Even if this text is veryshort, it is extremely rich and interesting.One commentator has gone so far as to say that Leibniz’s encounter with Pascal gave him the occasion to succinctly summarize the whole of his own philosophy.[17] Even if this is overstated, there is some truth to the remark. The text is indeed one of the most succinct, condensed – and I would say beautiful – expressions of Leibniz’s philosophy at the time that his monadological phase begins to take shape.[18]
In any event, the text certainly merits more attention than it has received in the English-speaking world.[19] Indeed, part of my motivation here is to draw attention to this text, as well as to provide a new English translation of its first version. Another part of my motivation is to highlight and articulate some of the neglected philosophical significance of the text. I focus on Leibniz’s usage of infinity, in contrast to Pascal’s, and especially his attempt to capture the nature of living things – a topic that has received little attention in any of the previous commentaries on the text. I certainly do not wish to suggest that this is the exclusive significance of the text; but it is an important topic that has received very little attention. In particular, I attempt to bring out the contrast between the two central images – that of Pascal’s mite (ciron), which is a standard illustration of a minute animal in the pre-microscope era, and that of Leibniz’s living mirror (miroir vivant) – to capture the way infinity figures in their respective depictions of living beings.[20] In light of the current interest in the life sciences of the early modern period in general, and Leibniz’s views in particular, revisiting the text from this particular angle seems timely.[21]
In sections 2-5, I present the text and the major differences between Pascal’s and Leibniz’s uses of infinity in describing the nature of living things. In section 6, I offer an account of the content of the text and its appearance around 1696 by looking at the role Leibniz’s view of infinity plays in his definition of living beings in the New System of Nature. In section 7, I argue that, in spite of superficial similarities, Leibniz’s use of infinity to define living beings stands in stark contrast to Pascal’s use of infinity. Whereas Pascal uses infinity to emphasize divisibility and disparity, alongside our inability to comprehend the infinite world surrounding us, Leibniz uses infinity to emphasize the intrinsic unity that each living being must have, the inherent harmony among all living beings, and our sense of belonging to an infinite world precisely because we, as imitations of an absolutely infinite being, are infinite too (though to a lesser degree).
2. The Text
As already noted, sometime around 1696, Leibniz was busy copying fragment 22 of the so-called Port-Royal edition of Pascal’s Pensées. Once he was done with what looks like a hasty (and imprecise) transcription,Leibniz turned to compose a comment. His comment begins with a dramatic and curious statement:
“Ce que Mons. Pascal dit de la double infinité, qui nous environne en augmentant et en diminuant, lorsque dans ses Pensées (n. 22) il parle de la connaissance générale de l’homme, n’est qu’une entrée dans mon système”(version 2 (folio 213 r-v) in De Buzon p. 554).
What M. Pascal says of the double infinity, which surrounds us while increasing and decreasing, when in his Pensées (n. 22) he speaks of the general knowledge of man, is but an entry point into my system.
Leibniz proceeds to write asingle page comment. The importance of this textwasalready noted by Gerhardt in 1891[22] and then by Baruzi in 1907;[23]it was reedited byGrua in 1948 under the charming title “Double infinité chez Pascal et Monade,” which facilitatedfurther commentaries by Guitton[24], Costable[25], Serres[26], Naërt[27], McKenna[28], and Carraud[29],among others. While there are a fair number of commentaries on this text in French, to the best of my knowledge there is none in English. Even in French, there is very little in the existing literature on the implications of Leibniz’s comment for his view of living things. With the recent commentary by Frédéric de Buzon,this too is beginning to change.[30] In 2010, de Buzon publisheda commentary in which he notes the significance of Leibniz’s notion of natural machine vis-à-vis Pascal, as well asproviding a new edition that presents two different versions of the text in meticulous detail.The first version is a marginal comment added to a transcription of the passage from the Pensées, with the note, “Was am Rande von mir addiert, habe ich besser auf ein ander Papier geschrieben.” The second version is an expansion of the marginal note, now on a separate piece of paper.While de Buzon emphasizes the similarity between Leibniz’s notion of a natural machine and Pascal’s view, I argue that there are significant differences in their views, which are also expressed in the images they use.
De Buzon’s publication is the immediate occasion for the present article, as well as the source for the text translated into English here. Since the text is dense and difficult to translate, I first cite it in French (in De Buzon’s version) and then offer a translation. The first version of Leibniz’s response to Pascal reads as follows:
Jusqu’ici M. Pascal. <Was am Rande von mir addiert, habe ich besser auf ein ander Papier geschrieben.> Ce qu’il vient de dire de la double infinité n’est qu’une entrée dans mon système. Que n’aurait-il pas dit, avec cette force d’éloquence qu’il possédait, s’il y était venu plus avant, s’il avait su que toute la matière est organique, et que la moindre portion contient, par l’infinité actuelle de ses parties, d’une infinité de façons, un miroir vivant exprimant tout l’univers infini, de sorte qu’on y pourrait lire (si on avait la vue assez perçante aussi bien que l’esprit) non seulement le présent étendu à l’infini, mais encor le passé, et tout l’avenir [infini pour chaque moment] infiniment infini, puisqu’il est infini par chaque moment, et qu’il y a une infinité de moments dans chaque partie du temps, et plus d’infinité qu’on ne saurait dire dans toute l’éternité future. Mais l’harmonie préétablie passe encore tout cela et donne cette même infinité universelle dans chaque [presque néant] <premier presque néant (qui est en même temps le dernier presque tout et le seul pourtant qui mérite d’être appelé une substance après Dieu) c’est- à-dire dans chaque point réel, qui fait une Monade, dont moi j’en suis une, et ne périra non plus que Dieu et l’univers, qu’il doit toujours représenter, étant [un Dieu] [comme Dieu] en même temps moins qu’un Dieu et plus qu’un univers de matière : un comme-Dieu diminutif, et un comme-univers éminemment, et comme prototype, les mondes intelligibles étant en ectype les sources du monde sensible dans les idées de Dieu.
Here is my English translation:
Up until here it is Pascal. What he just said of the double infinity is nothing but an entry point to my system. What wouldn’t he have said with his powerful eloquence if he had advanced further, if he had known that all matter is organic, and that the least portion contains, through the actual infinity of its parts, a living mirror expressing all the infinite universe in an infinity of ways, so that one could read in it (if one had a sufficiently penetrating sight and mind) not only the present extended to infinity but also the past and all the future [infinite at each moment] infinitely infinite, since it is infinite at any moment and there are infinity of moments in any part of time, and more infinity than one could ever say in all of future eternity? But the pre-established harmony goes beyond all that and captures this same universal infinity in each primary almost-nothing (which is at the same time the final almost-everything [presque tout] and the only thing which deserves to be called a substance after God), that is, in each real point, which makes a Monad, of which I am one, and will not perish anymore than God or the universe, which it must always represent, being at the same time, less than God and more than the material universe: as a diminutive-God and an eminent universe, and as a prototype, the intelligible worlds being in ectype the sources of the sensible world in God’s ideas.
This is obviously a complex text. It contains several astounding claims. First, Leibniz claims that Pascal does not realize that all matter is organic. This indicates that Leibniz is presupposing his panorganic view that all beings are ultimately composed of living beings.[31] Second, organic matter is actually divided to infinity. This is a familiar theme, which is present in Leibniz’s work since his early writings. Third, and perhaps most remarkable as well as most novel, is the claim that, however small, each portion of matter contains a living mirror that expresses the infinitely large universe. The mirroring Leibniz notes here is due not merely to the actual division of matter to infinity but also to the existence of something living and active in each portion of matter. Fourth, such a living mirror contains “not only the present extended to infinity but also the past and all the future,” which is reminiscent of Leibniz’s doctrine of marks and traces that he ascribes to individual substances in the Discourse on Metaphysics (articles 8 and 13) and elsewhere. Fifth, Leibniz’s new system of preestablished harmony goes beyond all that in showing that such a living mirror, however minute and particular, captures universal infinity: in being almost nothing but at the same time almost all, it is the only real point that makes a Monad, which (sixth) deserves to be called the only real substance besides God, and (seventh) of which I am one; (eighth) it is like a diminutive-God, and thus (ninth) it will not perish and (tenth) will always represent God and the universe (in being a living mirror).
Surely my dissection of this dense text into a list of claims can be contested. What cannot be contested, I think, is that Leibniz brings together here some of his familiar theses with some new ones in a remarkable and dense text. Since this is one of the earliest appearances of the term ‘monad’ as well as the expression ‘living mirror’, it is not obvious how to interpret these notions in this context. It is fairly clear, however, that, in this passage, a living mirror is likened to a substance and that it makes a monad, which is both active and representative; and, that it is exemplified through the I. The I, the Ego, or Moy, are recurrent examples of the true unity of substance that Leibniz uses in many other texts, both earlier and later than this one. I believe that this example is significant. It suggests that by ‘living mirror’ (as well as by ‘monad’), Leibniz intends here to refer to a complete and true substance, rather than to some constituent of it. But, what does the qualification of a mirror as living add to the figure of a mirror simpliciter that Leibniz had already used in earlier texts? The qualification of a mirror as living indicates something important about the way Leibniz sees the mirroring relation and the capacity of each substance, however small, to represent the world.
In the reading I will develop below, this representation is accounted for both (1) by virtue of replication of internal structure among all living substances (in particular, their common infinite structure); and (2) by virtue of the active perception of each natural machine or living substance. The active representation, which I shall ascribe to a natural machine, is grounded in the form or entelechy, which is a principle of perception. One might say that there are two types of mirroring going on: 1) the infinite structure of the machine mirrors the universe, by changing in ways that track changes everywhere in the universe; 2) this mirroring is able to occur because the machine is unified by a form, which itself is a "living mirror" representing the infinite structure of its body and, hence, of the universe as a whole. In this way, Leibniz’s two means of accounting for the mirroring relations are connected to one another.[32]
Leibniz’s text raises other interesting questions. For example, what is the status of the term ‘monad’ at this period and how does it compare with the later usage of monad in texts such as the Monadologyand the Principles of Nature and Grace? I will touch on this question toward the end of the paper. In the next two sections, I am mainly interested in presenting the following theme. Like Pascal, Leibniz conceives of human beings as placed between two infinities. Yet, unlike Pascal, for Leibniz, human beings (as well as other living beings) are themselves seen as infinite creatures; and, as such, they are placed between the absolute infinity of God and infinitely divisible matter. As we shall see, Leibniz’s notion of the infinite is quite different from Pascal’s. Whereas,for Pascal, humans are seen as finite creatures facing and realizing their place between the infinitely vast and the infinitely minute, for Leibniz, humans are placed high up on a scale of a graded hierarchy of infinity and perfection – “the only thing which deserves to be called a substance after God… but at the same time, less than God and more than the material universe: as a diminutive-God and an eminent universe.”