GHJPM Neoliberalism Supplement

By Zach Babat, Matt Cole, Scotty P, Kevin Ryu, Chait Sayani, Madi Stephens, Erica Tashma.

America Bad Links

Simplistic politics about the US being bad hurts conceptual clarity. We need to focus struggle on specific criticisms.

North 1 David North and David Walsh 22 September 2001 http://www.wsws.org/en/articles/2001/09/rads-s22.html

A case in point is an article that appeared in the Guardian, the British daily newspaper, on September 18, authored by Charlotte Raven, a former member of the Militant Tendency, editor of the now-defunct Modern Review and currently a semi-celebrity and professional cynic. The piece is headlined, “A bully with a bloody nose is still a bully,” the bully in question being the US. In the first place, the September 11 tragedy was not “a bloody nose,” it was a catastrophe. Thousands of people were incinerated instantly when the airplanes hit the buildings, thousands more died when tons of rubble collapsed on them. Anyone who was emotionally unaffected by the terror and suffering experienced by tens of thousands as a result of this attack has no right to call himself or herself a socialist. Raven writes: “It is perfectly possible to condemn the terrorist action and dislike the US just as much as you did before the WTC went down. Many will have woken up on Wednesday with that combination of emotions... America is the same country it was before September 11. If you didn’t like it then, there’s no reason why you should have to pretend to now.” Raven’s references to “the US,” full stop, is no slip of the pen. It is repeated throughout the article. She never once uses the phrase “the US government” or “the US ruling elite”, or an equivalent. Using nationality as an epithet is always reactionary. Confronted with the most monstrous government in history, Hitler’s Nazi regime, socialists never descended to referring with contempt to “Germany” or “the Germans.” To present “the US” as some predatory imperialist monolith, as Raven and others do, can only confuse and disorient. It not only serves as a barrier to genuine internationalism, it overlooks the contradictory character of American history and society. What does it mean to “dislike the US”? What sort of social element speaks like this? The United States is a complex entity, with a complex history, elements of which are distinctly ignoble, elements of which are deeply noble. The US has passed through two revolutions—the American Revolution and the Civil War—the mass battles of the Depression and the struggle for Civil Rights. The contradiction between the democratic ideals and revolutionary principles on which the nation was founded and its social and political realities has always been the starting point of the struggle for socialism in the United States. The US was, if one considers the relationship between theory and politics, the product of the great Enlightenment. It established political principles, embodied in the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution, rather than religion or ethnicity, as the basis of national identity. This origin of the nation in the struggle for abstract ideals—democracy, republicanism—reverberated across the globe. The American Revolution played no small role in inspiring the events that transformed France a decade later. Even after 200 years, the United States is still fighting through the political and historical implications of its own founding principles. The American population, polyglot and highly diverse, is obsessed with ideological problems, although its approach is often maddeningly pragmatic. As the popular response to the Bush hijacking of the 2000 election demonstrated, there remains a deep commitment to elementary democratic principles. A low level of class consciousness and the failure of masses of Americans to generalize from their experiences, however, provides the ruling elite the opportunity to play on precisely these democratic notions in order to blind layers of the population temporarily as to the true nature of its plans. For Bush and his ilk “defending freedom and democracy” is merely a code phrase for the right of the American elite to have its way around the world. To the ordinary American citizen, these words mean something quite different. The sinister reality of the US government’s new “war against terrorism,” with its grandiose aim of reorganizing an entire region of the world in line with American geopolitical interests, will make its way into popular consciousness providing the necessary work is conducted by socialist internationalists. In many ways all the vast problems in the struggle for socialism find their most complex expression in America. How could that not be the case? If one cannot find points of departure for a higher form of social organization in the US, in what corner of the globe are they to be found? What’s more, the individual who sees no basis for socialism in America clearly has given up on the prospects of world socialism altogether. The Marxist has always been distinguished from the common or garden variety radical by his or her deep confidence in the revolutionary potential of the American working class. In this regard, the US ruling elite has a much greater insight into the true nature of American society than the blinkered radical. The American bourgeoisie inveighs night and day against socialism and communism, in a manner far out of proportion to the threat currently posed by the socialist movement in the US, because it understands or at least senses instinctively that in the most advanced capitalist society, all things being equal, socialism offers such a rational and attractive alternative. America is, at once, the most advanced and the most backward of societies. Its culture attracts and repels, but always fascinates. Official society and many ordinary Americans deny the very existence of distinct social classes, and yet the country is riven by the most profound and ever-deepening social differentiation. These social contradictions will only be exacerbated, as the economic developments of this week have already shown, as the war drive proceeds. The US has produced Franklin, Washington, Jefferson and Lincoln, as well as extraordinary working class and socialist leaders. Its immense contradictions are perhaps exemplified by the figure of Jefferson, the slave-owner who wrote one of the greatest and most sincere hymns to human freedom. Raven continues, resorting to the terminology of Postmodernist drivel: “When America speaks from its heart, it retreats into a language that none but its true-born citizens can begin to understand. At the root of this is an overwhelming need to control meaning. America can’t let the world speak for itself. It was taken unawares last Tuesday and part of the trauma of that event was the shock of being forced to listen to a message that it hadn’t had time to translate. The subsequent roar of anger was, amongst other things, the sound of the US struggling to regain the right to control its own narrative.” If Raven is speaking of George W. Bush and other servants of American imperial interests, then the first sentence has no meaning. Such people clearly don’t speak from the heart on this or any other occasion; they are in the business of lying and deceiving. But pardon us for pointing out that, in fact, when “America,” in the form of its greatest political and cultural representatives, has spoken “from its heart,” millions around the world have listened and understood, beginning in the aftermath of July 4, 1776. The most advanced British workers certainly paid attention to the issuing of the Emancipation Proclamation on January 1, 1863. One could mention the appeals to the international working class on behalf of Sacco and Vanzetti and numerous other examples. And such instances, we hazard to predict, will occur in the future too. One might add that the finest products of American culture have also attracted and moved masses of people around the world, from Poe and Whitman, Melville and Hawthorne, in the 19th century, to Dreiser, Fitzgerald, Richard Wright and others in the 20th. Nor should one entirely forget the influence of American music, popular and otherwise. A few people, one imagines, have heard it speaking from the heart. This to say nothing of contributions with international implications in film, painting, sculpture, dance and architecture. Raven apparently counts upon her readers being so consumed by subjective venom and their own self-importance that they overlook obvious historical and cultural realities. It has always been an essential task of socialists in the US to awaken the positive and generous instincts that are so deeply embedded in the American population. There are, after all, two Americas, the America of Bush, Clinton and the other scoundrels, and another America, of its working people. Revolutionary internationalists have continuously insisted on this. James P. Cannon, the leader of the American Trotskyists, devoted a speech to this theme in July 1948. Of the “Two Americas” he observed: “One is the America of the imperialists—of the little clique of capitalists, landlords, and militarists who are threatening and terrifying the world. This is the America the people of the world hate and fear. There is the other America—the America of the workers and farmers and the ‘little people.’ They constitute the great majority of the people. They do the work of the country. They revere its old democratic traditions—its old record of friendship for the people of other lands, in their struggles against Kings and Despots—its generous asylum once freely granted to the oppressed.” The struggle against the policies and designs of the American government requires, in the first instance, the exposure of the latter’s claim that it is the true voice and representative of the people. Socialists are obliged to explain that the US ruling elite is carrying out anti-democratic and rapacious policies, with inevitably tragic consequences, in the pursuit of which it falsely invokes the name of the American people. All this of course is a closed book to the smug middle class philistine and snob, satisfied to make use of words and phrases that come most easily to hand. Raven’s variety of anti-Americanism is no more original than it is insightful. It is available cheaply and in large quantities in middle class circles in Britain, France, Germany and, for that matter, in the United States. It is available, so to speak, “on tap.” Such an outlook has the virtue of appearing oppositional, while not committing its adherent to any course of political action that might cause inconvenience. It is a form of pseudo-socialism, the phony “anti-imperialism” of cynics and fools.

Agamben

The 1AC perpetuates neoliberalism

Gambetti 11 (Zeynep, Arendt and Foucault On Market Logic: Security, Violence, and Superfluousness, https://www.academia.edu/532833/Arendt_and_Foucault_on_market_logic_security_violence_and_superfluousness, 4/15/11)

The central thesis of Giorgio Agamben’s political philosophy, as expressed in Homo Sacer , is that “the politicization of bare life as such […] constitutes the decisive event of modernity” (Agamben, 1998, 4). Drawing among others upon Hannah Arendt’s analysis of the totalitarian concentration camp and Michel Foucault’s conceptualization of biopolitical power, Agamben seeks to remedy a lacuna that he detects in both: that of the exact relation between the camp and biopower. To this end, he turns to otherthinkers, notably Carl Schmitt, from whom he borrows the theory of sovereignty. This allows Agamben to reframe the question of biopower in such a way that it reveals the hidden ground of politics and finds its paradigmatic example in the camp. 1 As such Agamben hopes to “bring the political out of its concealment and, at the same time, return thought to its practical calling” (5). As challenging and meaningful such an enterprise may be, it nevertheless falls short of accomplishing its avowed goal. Agamben obscures the relation between violence and the market fundamentalism of neoliberalism, a matter of much concern foranyone heeding the practical calling of thought. The overpoliticization of bare life in Homo Sacer in turn conceals the complex and intricate relationship between the economic and the political. The problem with Agamben’s analysis has to do with the ontological status of “politics”. Organicism pervades the whole of Homo Sacer . The language of “incorporation” discloses what remains explicit in Agamben’s political metaphysics:politics is conceived as an ordered body, a whole, an identity and a determination. The outside of this body is not negativity as such but another body, a biological one. The identity-thinking that this construal is grounded upon (Norris, 2000, 42-43) cannot have an outside, since antagonism is built into it: the political is political because it is not barelife, or rather, the political defines itself at the same time as it defines what it is not, barelife. Politics is reduced to a dichotomous system of relating that comprises a project, a nomos , which can never be stabilized once and for all. It does not come as a surprise, then, that Agamben should use Aristotle’s teleological construal of politics as the tending towards the “good life” as an argument upon which to ground his metaphysics of the exclusion of bare life from the political (Agamben, 1998, 7). The only exception that can be imagined in his universe is indistinction, not aufhebung . Since politics is a self-reflexive form-giving, it exhausts itself in pure positivity, the negation of the negation is a 1 Agamben also draws upon Benjamin, Heidegger, Nancy and Bataille, but the focus of this paper is exclusively on Arendt and Foucault. 3 moment that never comes. The sovereign exception, “the figure in which singularity is represented as such, which is to say, insofar as it is unrepresentable” (Agamben, 1998,24), is what Agamben paradoxically tends to represent throughout his analysis, beginning with the figure of homo sacer , passing through the Müselmann , and ending with Karen Quinlan. Thus, as Andrew Norris strikingly underlines, Agamben’s decision to erect the camp into the exemplary norm that characterizes the modern is itself an act of sovereignty that “puts him in the position of deciding upon the camp victims one more time, thereby repeating the gesture of the ss [ sic ] in precisely the way he says we mustavoid” (Norris, 2005, 278). As such, he is unable to conceptualize singularity, but only antagonism in the sense Laclau and Mouffe use it (1985, 122-127). The trouble is that by conflating politics with sovereign form-giving and, subsequently, sovereignty with every distinction that may exist in the humanly constructed world (language, body, life, form, fact, right, law, exception, example,decision), Agamben has indeed already rendered indistinct any distinction to be made between politics and other phenomena. The circle is squared with the concept of biopolitics, since Agamben’s account of sovereignty is already biopolitical – it hinges upon a conception of the political that defines itself in relation to life, only if to exclude it. Thus, what appears to be “the politicization of life” in the modern era cannot be grasped in Agamben’s perspective since life is construed as always-already defined by apolitical decision. As such, the difference between the Greek polis and the modernnation-state, the nation-state and Empire is effaced. As a matter of fact, there is a huge inconsistency in Homo Sacer that reveals itself as soon as we move into the third part of the book on biopolitics. The indistinction between zoe and bios is to have been caused by a crisis in sovereignty such that the whole earth is now functioning on the basis of states of exception. Yet, the capacity to decide upon states of exception is still construed as a sign of sovereignty – there seems to be no crisis, after all. In fact, while it seems that the only difference between classical politics and biopolitics is the expansion of domains of sovereign decision, the latter already comprises the most fundamental activities of human existence such as speech since time immemorial. The metaphysical account of sovereignty makes it impossible to grasp what is at stake in biopolitics proper, i.e. in specifically modern politics in such a way as to make sense of the Agambenian rendition of biopolitics as the destabilization of the otherwise stable border between life and death (Agamben, 1998, 122). It may well be that sovereignty has been dissolved in such a way as to dissolve along with it any criteria for judging whether a situation is an exception or not.